Dado un conjunto N tendente a infinito es inevitable que absolutamente todo suceda, siempre que se disponga de tiempo suficiente o infinito , y he ahí donde está el verdadero problema irresoluble o quid de la cuestión de la existencia ¿quién nos garantiza que dispongamos del tiempo necesario para que ocurra lo que debe o deseamos que suceda?


lunes, 29 de septiembre de 2025

149. 51. The Reliability of Science and Statistics, the Dialectic of Reliability, Theoretical Reliability

 51. The Reliability of Science and Statistics, the Dialectic of Reliability, Theoretical Reliability

 

51.1. Political Decisions and Reliability in Scientific Policy

From an anthropological perspective, human beings require the safeguarding of their survival by minimizing, as much as possible, the moral margin of error in political decisions. Inversely, this entails maximizing the ethical reliability of such decisions. Scientific decisions, insofar as they are dependent upon scientific policy—and by extension, upon the political ideology underpinning such policy—are, in essence, political decisions. This means that the acceptance of moral risk margins, expressed through the establishment of thresholds of factual or rational error and reliability, whether applied to empirical samples or to the rational critique of ideas, ultimately rests on political choices framed by scientific policy.

The significance of the reliability of a given model of scientific policy—irrespective of whether it represents a dominant or an alternative paradigm—lies in the necessity of trustworthy practices to achieve its guiding ideals. Chief among these is the ideal of truth, upon which all other scientific ideals morally depend. Importantly, the interpretation of truth is not absolute; rather, it varies according to the prevailing model of scientific policy. This dependence of truth on policy is extensively discussed in section 24 of Introduction to Impossible Probability, where the relationship between ideology, politics, and the acceptance of truth as a scientific criterion is elaborated.

 

51.2. Reliability and Error as Dialectical Opposites

Reliability may be defined as certainty. It exists in a relationship of inverse proportionality with error: the greater the reliability, the smaller the margin of error, and vice versa. Thus, reliability and error stand as opposites in much the same way that certainty and uncertainty are opposed. However, within the frameworks of materialist and idealist dialectics, such opposites are not only contraries but also identical in their relation: each exists by virtue of the other. The dialectical view therefore regards error and reliability as two faces of the same phenomenon, whose tension defines the limits of knowledge, truth, and scientific validity.

This conceptualization situates reliability not as an absolute quality but as a relational category that gains meaning only against its opposite. Insofar as error must always be accepted to some degree, reliability is never perfect or final but relative, historically situated, and conditioned by the epistemological frameworks in use.

 

51.3. The Subject–Object Dialectic in Impossible Probability

The development of the statistical theory of probability—or what is here termed statistical probability—within the framework of Impossible Probability is grounded in a dialectical vision. At its core lies the dialectic of subject and object, which finds mathematical representation in the relation between subject and option. This foundational duality is introduced as early as section 1, where differential analysis provides the groundwork for later distinctions between empirical probability and theoretical probability.

According to the dialectical principle, every thesis engenders its own antithesis. Applied to the field of reliability, this means that every degree of reliability necessarily implies a corresponding degree of error, just as every degree of error simultaneously implies the presence of some measure of reliability. This interplay is not merely a logical curiosity but a structural necessity of statistical reasoning. It ensures that the science of probability is perpetually self-critical, always oscillating between the poles of certainty and uncertainty in its pursuit of truth.

 

51.4. Logic, Ethics, and the Reliability of Science

The reliability of science is nothing other than its degree of certainty. A science that proves false is, by definition, unreliable. Consequently, within cycles of crisis and scientific revolution, only the most reliable scientific models ought to prevail. Nevertheless, history demonstrates that, for political and ideological reasons, models devoid of logical coherence have often dominated intellectual landscapes for extended periods.

A fundamental characteristic of reliability is its dependence on logic. For something to be reliable, it must first be logically consistent, and by extension, ethically sound. A science that lacks logical structure and ethical grounding can only be regarded as entirely false. Conversely, a science that is sufficiently logical or sufficiently ethical may sustain an adequate scientific discourse, even if it is not completely isomorphic with reality. Yet, because science necessarily operates within the contradiction between reality-in-itself and political reality-for-itself, crises in scientific development are inevitable. Reliability, therefore, is always provisional, contingent on both logical and ethical coherence, and permanently exposed to the dialectical tension between truth and error.

 

51.5. Reliability in Empirical and Technological Hypotheses

Reliability, in its most fundamental sense, is equivalent to certainty. Within empirical explanatory hypotheses, reliability refers to the certainty achieved in establishing causal or correlational links between variables. For example, an explanatory model in the social sciences is only reliable to the extent that the causal attribution between two variables can withstand empirical and rational scrutiny.

In the case of technological hypotheses, reliability is understood as the certainty that a given technology will produce results aligned with the ideals of efficiency and efficacy required by scientific policy. Thus, the reliability of technology is not only a matter of functional success but also of political and ethical alignment, since technological outcomes are expected to serve the broader goals set by the prevailing scientific paradigm. In both contexts—explanatory and technological—reliability acts as the measure of how far empirical evidence and practical applications can be trusted to achieve outcomes that are scientifically valid and ethically legitimate.

 

51.6. Reliability de facto and Rational Reliability

Because reliability is the dialectical opposite of error, the two must be understood as identical in their relational structure: to accept a margin of error is to accept, inversely, a margin of reliability; and to accept a margin of reliability is to acknowledge, inversely, a margin of error. This interdependence underscores the impossibility of absolute certainty in science.

Within Impossible Probability, two distinct forms of theoretical error are identified—de facto error and rational error. Correspondingly, there exist two types of theoretical reliability:

  • Reliability de facto, which is inversely proportional to the margin of de facto error arising from empirical limitations such as sample representativeness.
  • Rational reliability, which is inversely proportional to the rational error allowed by scientific policy in the critical evaluation of ideas [the critical reason, the critical probability].

These two modes of reliability, one grounded in the empirical necessity of sampling and the other in the rational acceptance of ideological or methodological limits, together delineate the full spectrum of reliability in scientific inquiry.

[In the case of GAI, it could be suggested that GAI lacks ideology, but this is not true. As long as it is a system of ideas—the categorical system, the conceptual scheme, the conceptual map, the conceptual models—it is an ideal construction of reality, essentially built upon a definition of efficacy and efficiency. The simple act of defining conceptual decisions based on ideals of efficiency and efficacy is an ideological act. While for the defenders of the free market—such as the United States—efficiency and efficacy may be central, this definition may not be the same for the defenders of socialism. At present, the most important model of socialism is China {note that we do not refer to China as a communist society, even if this is the ultimate goal of China; right now, China is state capitalism, in other words, socialism}. What is important to highlight about China is how it has been able to achieve a very significant level of AI development, even further than other countries based on the free market, such as Japan or the United Kingdom. If this book is no the place for an ideological debate, it would be advisable to analyse which characteristics of the social state of China have contributed to this advancement. In 1949, the United Kingdom was still an empire, and China had just ended its civil war. In 2025, the United Kingdom is in decline, and China is a superpower. The relationship between China and the United Kingdom is, obviously, inversely proportional. But we need to acknowledge that in future models of Global AI, the differences between the Global Artificial Intelligence of America and the Chinese version will not only be grounded in the types of algorithms used, but also in how each team in the race will train their respective AI models according to different concepts of efficacy and efficiency, based on their political agendas. In other words, directly or indirectly, the Global Artificial Intelligence of America will be trained under a very clear pro-capitalist ideology, while the Chinese version will be trained under a very clear agenda of socialism with Chinese characteristics. In short, all Global AI will be the replication of an ideological program, and its purpose will be to apply a global ideological agenda based on the ideology in which it has been programmed.

In other words, those agendas seeking to promote global justice and equality must work on developing their own Global AI models if they want to succeed in the competition for global dominance in AI. Otherwise, it might only be achievable through an international order, by establishing some form of international agreement regulating the limits and legal frameworks of these supermachines in order to ensure that they serve the common good.

The ideas of Marx and Engels about the future leadership of the proletariat do not make sense in a future dominated by machines. Our opinion is that the working class will be banished. The dictatorship of the proletariat will never happen, because there will no longer be a proletariat. Something different is the building of the social utopia, which dates back to Thomas More, and even much earlier. Anarchism and communal property were the very first forms of social organisation among human tribes in the Palaeolithic, where what the men hunted and the women gathered was shared by the whole tribe, without class distinctions, and where hierarchy in the decision-making process was not about creating an Orwellian global order of control or a new technological feudalism.

From our perspective, at some point we need to reconsider the very nature of the concept of work and the social system itself. With our current AI, work can be automated, unemployment will be massive, and we will need to rethink social values and modes of organisation without discarding any ideal. Anarchism and socialism, like the model pursued in China, are still valid frameworks—provided they can adapt to our Cyborg Revolution. At this point of cold war between the US and China, it is important to remember Henry Kissinger as the man who made peace between these two countries possible.]

 

51.7. Anthropological Limitations and the Relativity of Reliability

The reason reliability can never be absolute is rooted in the anthropological condition of the human being. Humans are inherently limited, incomplete, and inconsistent. As such, the mathematical reliability of any phenomenon can never be total or perfect. Nothing is absolutely reliable; at best, it is partially or incompletely reliable.

This means that reliability is never impartial or neutral. It is always relative, partial, and inevitably ideological, because it depends on the scientific policy and the ideological commitments underpinning it. Thus, every assertion of reliability reflects not only an epistemic state of knowledge but also the political and moral framework within which that knowledge is evaluated.

[Even in this paragraph we can grasp an idea of why Global AI cannot escape the reality of ideology. As long as, even for GAI, de facto error and sampling are necessary, it cannot know the entirety of the universe—it can only acquire partial knowledge. And all knowledge, as long as it is partial, is not neutral; it is, in essence, ideological. At some point, this is something that even the supermachine is going to inherit from us.]

 

51.8. Human Contradiction and the Necessity of Rational Critique

As developed in section 2 and expanded in section 7 on the infinite, the anthropological and philosophical need for reliability arises directly from the contradictory and dialectical nature of the human being. From the rationalist perspective, the human is a synthesis of res cogitans (thinking substance) and res extensa (extended substance), a synthesis of objectivity and subjectivity, reason and emotion.

This duality ensures that the human being can never be absolutely objective or rational, because part of their constitution is irreducibly subjective and emotional. Human subjectivity and emotion derive from the material and physiological nature of the species. A being that is necessarily empirical can never be fully logical. This is the contradiction between matter and form, which is critically resolved in the human entity through the exercise of rational critique.

The necessity of rationally criticizing ideas of reality stems from this condition: the goal is to reach the most objective possible approximation to reality, even if never complete. At best, humans can achieve a certain degree of isomorphism between idea and reality, but never perfect correspondence. This is why reliability is always partial, contingent, and in need of constant rational evaluation.

 

51.9. The Origin of Error and the Antinomy of Science

The empirical limitations of the human being in the face of the infinite constitute the origin of error. As explained in section 7, human self-awareness of its own subjectivity and emotionality prevents the attainment of absolute certainty. Consequently, absolute reliability remains a utopia, at least at the present stage of scientific development.

This condition makes the first Kantian categorical imperative—to transform actions into universal maxims—an impossibility or utopia in the domain of science. Science today can only ever be partially true, operating within margins of error or reliability set by scientific policy. But if a science is only partially true, it must also be partially false. This leads to a logical antinomy: science is simultaneously true and false.

We recognize that, within accepted margins of error, current science is true. Yet we also acknowledge that its truth extends only until the point at which the inevitable margin of error becomes manifest, at which moment the falsity of science materializes. Science is thus a dynamic and antinomic enterprise, oscillating between partial truth and inevitable error.

 

51.10. The Relationship Between Reliability and Margins of Error in Science

Science is true to the extent that it is reliable, and it is reliable in inverse proportion to the margins of error accepted by scientific policy. These margins—whether theoretical, de facto, or rational—constitute the critical boundaries of reason.

In this sense, scientific truth is not absolute but proportional. The more restrictive the margins of error allowed by policy, the greater the reliability of scientific outcomes; conversely, the broader the acceptance of error, the weaker the reliability of scientific truth. This proportionality reveals the inherently critical dimension of science, in which truth is not static but constantly redefined through the dialectical interplay of error and reliability.

 

 51.11. Differentiation Between Theoretical Error and Empirical Error

Within the framework of Impossible Probability, error is not a monolithic category but must be differentiated into distinct forms. On the one hand, there are theoretical errors, which include both de facto error (arising from the necessity of sampling) and rational error (arising from the acceptance of ideological or methodological limits imposed by scientific policy). On the other hand, there exists empirical error, which is irreducible to theoretical formulations.

This distinction carries with it a corollary: just as there are theoretical forms of reliability (corresponding to theoretical errors), there must also be empirical reliability, which reflects the degree of certainty achieved in practice when confronting data as they manifest in reality. The differentiation between theoretical and empirical error—and correspondingly between theoretical and empirical reliability—is essential for a comprehensive understanding of scientific validity, because it acknowledges both the rational-logical and the material-empirical dimensions of error.

 

51.12. Empirical Error and the Dispersion of Data

Whereas theoretical error is bounded by margins accepted either de facto (sampling limitations) or rationally (policy-driven choices), empirical error is bounded by the dispersion inherent in the data themselves. In other words, empirical error is a function of the variability of occurrences within the observed universe, and it depends directly on the object of study.

This form of error is addressed from section 16 onwards, where different contexts are distinguished—such as studies of equality of opportunity, positive bias, or omega models. Each of these cases requires specific treatment, since the dispersion and structure of empirical data vary according to the phenomenon under investigation. In the case of omega models, where multiple ideal options exist simultaneously within a given universe, empirical error takes on additional complexity, a theme explored in section 20.

[As I have said many times, I was born into a Marxist family. From the very beginning of Introduction to Impossible Probability, it is very clear that the target is the analysis of the relation between bias and equality. At that time, I was involved in the emergence of a social revolution in Madrid, the 15M movement, and later I became a member of the anarchist union CGT, and afterwards of Solidaridad Obrera (Workers’ Solidarity). Even in London I maintained contact with anarchists (Solidarity Federation) and Marxist organisations (Socialist Workers Party, Newham branch).

We must not forget that José Rodríguez Delgado was a disciple of Juan Negrín. This is the very origin of Cyborg Robotics in Spain: Civil War, dictatorship, and the Cold War between the US and Russia. In that context, I wrote the book and this blog. At that time, my ideology was rooted in social equality. Understanding how Impossible Probability was born makes it easy to see why dispersion was identified as empirical error, because the theory itself was born under a very progressive agenda pursuing social justice.

Throughout my whole life I have been oscillating between different ideologies, even oscillating between different genders. Oscillations between different philosophies and sexual orientations have taught me to love and to learn who I am, and to recognise the importance of the Transhuman Revolution in the future adaptation of humans to our supermachine.

Something we need to learn from Henry Kissinger is the importance of being open to the future and to different ideologies. The point is not to destroy China or Russia, but to find ways to transform societies while working together, as Karl Pribram and Alexander Luria once did. This approach can also be applied to future transitions in Spain, future transitions in Europe, future transitions in Ukraine, and future transitions in the relations between the United Kingdom and Northern Ireland. In his last years, Henry Kissinger was a clear advocate for peace in Taiwan, peace in Ukraine, and peace in Europe.]

 

51.13. Empirical Models of Error and Reliability

Section 16 further develops the empirical structure of chance (azar) and its relationship to reliability, by examining concrete models of empirical error and empirical reliability. These models are indispensable within what Impossible Probability terms inter-measurement statistics—a statistical approach that operates across multiple levels of interaction, whether intra-individual (within a single subject across conditions) or inter-individual (across multiple subjects) in different measurements.

The construction of such models demonstrates that error and reliability must be understood not only at the theoretical level but also as practical, empirical realities. The articulation of empirical error models ensures that the statistical treatment of variability remains faithful to the observed structure of data, rather than being subsumed entirely under abstract theoretical assumptions.

 

51.14. Synthesis of Theoretical Reliability

Given that much of the present discussion has focused on theoretical error, it is necessary at this point to synthesize the concept of theoretical reliability. While the details are already extensively developed in earlier sections—specifically section 3 (on the definition of reliability), section 5 (on the relation between reliability and truth), and section 11 (on rational error)—this synthesis serves to highlight the central principle: theoretical reliability is the inverse of theoretical error.

In Impossible Probability, theoretical reliability thus represents the degree of certainty that can be rationally and logically ascribed to scientific statements, contingent upon both empirical sampling and rational critique. Its synthesis consolidates the dialectical view that reliability and error are inseparable and that theoretical reliability is always relative to the margins of error one is prepared to accept.

 

51.15. De Facto Error and the Representativity of Samples

De facto error refers to the unavoidable error inherent in any scientific study that requires the acceptance of a sample. No matter how large or well-constructed the sample, the probability of error in representativity is always equal to the inverse of the sample size. Thus, to accept any sample is already to accept error.

Even if the sample size increases and the inverse approaches zero, the presence of error cannot be entirely eliminated. Over sufficient time or within an infinite horizon, every de facto error proves to be inevitable. This principle underscores the necessity of humility in scientific claims: representativity can be maximized but never rendered perfect. The reliance on samples is indispensable to statistics, yet it always entails a concession to error, a structural feature that no scientific method can overcome.

 

51.16. The Sample as an Essential Aspect of Impossible Probability

The definition of the sample emerges as a fundamental aspect of Impossible Probability, since the type of sample directly determines the degree of representativity error. In universes of infinite subjects or options—defined by the possibility of infinite singular qualities—the probability of representativity error is given by the inversion of N (the sample size). Consequently, Theoretical Reliability is necessarily equal to the difference between unity and the inversion of N:

 

 

 

This expression formalizes the structural relationship between sampling and reliability in infinite universes, showing that reliability can only be understood relative to the inverse of sample size.

 

51.17. The Tendency Toward Error in Infinite Universes

The meaning of de facto Theoretical Reliability is that, as N tends toward infinity in universes of infinite subjects or options, error tends toward zero and reliability tends toward its maximum possible value. However, within the framework of Impossible Probability, even if N were to reach infinity and the probability of representativity error were to tend toward zero, this does not imply the absolute elimination of error.

The reason is that even a probability that tends toward zero—expressed as an infinite series of decimal zeros—remains, in practice, an Impossible Probability:

 

A number with a white background

AI-generated content may be incorrect.

 

Although mathematically reducible to zero, the error remains structurally inevitable when considered in the context of infinite time. Thus, even in universes of infinite options, error cannot be annihilated but only minimized, confirming the principle that in a sufficient or infinite timeframe, error is always bound to emerge.

 

 

 

51.18. Theoretical Reliability in Universes of Limited Options

In universes where options are limited—whether by social or material constraints, as explained in section 9—the sample is defined by direct scores or frequencies. Even in such cases, it is possible to encounter infinite frequencies or occurrences, meaning that while the number of options is materially or socially finite, the frequencies associated with them may still be infinite.

This leads to a phenomenon analogous to that in infinite universes: if the sample of frequencies tends toward infinity, error, although tending toward zero, will remain inevitable—provided that the timeframe is sufficient or infinite.

Thus, in universes of limited options, the probability of representativity error is inversely proportional to the sample of direct scores or frequencies. Accordingly, Theoretical Reliability is expressed as:

 

 

This formulation demonstrates that the structural link between reliability and error persists, regardless of whether the universe of options is infinite or finite, though in limited universes it applies specifically to frequencies rather than to options themselves.

 

51.19. Theoretical Reliability and Rational Error in the Critique of Ideas

From this perspective, de facto Theoretical Reliability is inversely proportional to de facto error, and can be mathematically expressed as the difference between unity and the inversion of the sample. By contrast, rational reliability is inversely proportional to rational error and depends on the type of study being carried out within rational critique.

Whether a study is classified as a model of error or of reliability will depend on how rational error is conceptualized and on the criteria set by scientific policy. In this sense, rational reliability is not determined by empirical representativity but by the degree of error one is willing to accept when subjecting ideas to critical rational evaluation.

 

51.20. Studies of Error and Studies of Reliability

In Impossible Probability, a study may be classified either as an “error study” or a “reliability study” depending on whether the moral variable X is calculated in terms of a percentage of error or of reliability. This classification underscores the moral and political dimension inherent in scientific evaluation: whether one frames the object of analysis in terms of accepted error or accepted reliability is itself a decision shaped by scientific policy.

Thus, the designation of a study as an error-based model or a reliability-based model reveals more than methodological preference—it reflects the underlying philosophical and ethical assumptions guiding the research process. Error and reliability are not only technical categories but also moral and political categories embedded within the dialectical structure of Impossible Probability.

 

51.21. The Model of Equality Validity (Validez de Igualdad)

An illustrative case is the model of Equality Validity. In this model, critical probability is defined as the product of the Maximum Possible Theoretical Bias and a percentage X of error divided by one hundred. By definition, this constitutes a study of error, since the calculation is grounded in the acceptance of a percentage of error. Consequently, rational reliability is expressed as the complement of this percentage: one hundred minus X, or the percentage of reliability.

 

 

 

 

The formulation can be expressed as:

 

A white background with black and white numbers

AI-generated content may be incorrect.

 

Here, X represents the percentage of error, while 100 – X represents the corresponding percentage of reliability.

This formulation underscores the principle that the acceptance of error is unavoidable in critical rational analysis: equality can only be validated by recognizing, and quantifying, the permissible error margin.

 

51.22. The Model of Equality Significance (Significación de Igualdad)

In contrast, the model of Equality Significance shifts the focus from error to reliability. Here, the critical rational test is applied to the difference between the Maximum Possible Theoretical Bias and the absolute value of the Level of Bias. This difference is compared to a critical probability defined not in terms of error but in terms of reliability, expressed as a percentage X of reliability divided by one hundred.

 

 

 

 

 

 

The formulation is expressed as:

 

A math equations on a white background

AI-generated content may be incorrect.

 

Here, X represents the percentage of reliability, while represents the percentage of error.

In this model, the moral variable X is interpreted directly as reliability rather than error. This shift illustrates how the conceptual framing of a study—whether centered on error or reliability—determines its methodological and moral orientation.

 

51.23. Classification of Studies According to the Calculation of Critical Probability

From the preceding models it follows that, in general terms, studies can be classified as either “error studies” or “reliability studies,” depending on whether the critical probability is calculated as a percentage X of error or of reliability.

Thus:

  • Every error study will have a margin of rational reliability equal to one hundred minus the percentage of error accepted by scientific policy.
  • Conversely, every reliability study will have a margin of rational error equal to one hundred minus the percentage of reliability.

In both cases, the dialectical reciprocity holds: every acceptance of error entails the acceptance of reliability, and vice versa. Yet, crucially, the acceptance of rational error implies the recognition that, however reliable a model may be, error remains inevitable. Given sufficient or infinite time, everything possible—including what is initially deemed impossible—becomes inevitable.

 

51.24. The Dependence of Theoretical Reliability on Error

Theoretical reliability is structurally dependent upon theoretical error. This error may be of two types:

  • De facto error, which arises from the empirical necessity of working with a sample (since without a sample, no statistical analysis is possible). Therefore, one hundred minus the inversion of the sample equals de facto reliability.
  • Rational error, which reflects the acceptance of limits established by scientific policy in the rational critique of ideas. Therefore, one hundred minus the percentage X of critical error equals the percentage of reliability.

This dependence highlights the inseparability of reliability and error: the former can only be defined in relation to the latter.

 

51.25. The Difference Between De Facto Reliability and Rational Reliability

The distinction between the two forms of reliability can be formalized as follows:

  • De facto Reliability is always equal to unity minus the inversion of the sample, regardless of the type of universe under study.
  • Rational reliability, however, depends on the moral variable X, which represents the percentage of error or reliability accepted in the rational critique of ideas.

This dual structure makes explicit the twofold grounding of reliability: one in empirical necessity, the other in rational choice.

 

51.26. Empirical Reliability as a Necessary Complement

In addition to these models of reliability—whether de facto or rational—it is essential, within Impossible Probability, to acknowledge empirical reliability. Since every theoretical value is necessarily paired with an empirical value, empirical reliability must be taken into account alongside empirical error.

This consideration is indispensable for rational critique at the inter-measurement level (that is, in contexts where statistical analysis addresses interactions within or between subjects), as developed beginning in section 16.

 

51.27. The Inevitability of De Facto Error

Even if, at the theoretical level, one were to adopt a critical rational position accepting only 100% reliability and 0% rational error, the persistence of de facto error remains unavoidable. The reason is simple: the necessity of employing a sample. [ And this is unavoidable even for GAI, unless our supermachine could make infinite computations at the same time. As we have said many times, nothing is impossible given the right conditions; the point here is what conditions would be necessary to reach that level of intelligence. We, as humans, are not able to reach that point. The question is whether a Real Intelligence—not a limited human intelligence, but a true Real Intelligence—could be able to do that.].

The acceptance of a sample is simultaneously the acceptance of empirical reality, and with it, the inevitability of error in representativity. Without samples, there is no statistics; but every sample, by definition, carries error. Thus, reliability can never be absolute.

This principle also exposes the philosophical implication: accepting reality always entails accepting some measure of contradiction with our ideals. Science cannot escape the gap between what is empirically given and what is normatively desired. De facto error is therefore not only a statistical necessity but also an ontological condition of scientific knowledge.

 

 

This augmented translation is based on the post
published in https://probabilidadimposible.blogspot.com/,
On 3 March 2013,
Rubén García Pedraza
imposiblenever@gmail.com